Aquinas, Avicenna, Averroes on the Intellect 2013

Telechargé par C. Bordeleau
AQUINAS AND
'THE
ARABS':
AQUINAS'S
FIRST
CRITICAL
ENCOUNTER
WITH
THE
DOCTRINES
OF
A VICENNA AND A
VERROES
ON
THE
INTELLECT,
IN
2 SENT.
D.
17, Q. 2,
A.
11
Richard C.
TAYLOR
(Marquette University, Milwaukee)
Throughout his entire career as a theologian and philosophical thinker,
Thomas Aquinas was deeply concerned with the interpretation
of
Aristo-
telian teachings on the nature
of
the human soul and intellect as provided by
Averroes in the latter's Long Commentary on the
De
Anima
of
Aristotle
2.
As is well known, Aquinas engaged the reasoning
of
Latin followers
of
Averroes as well as that
of
Averroes himself in his polemical
De
unitate
intellectus contra averroistas written in 1270 by drawing upon arguments
already set forth in critical accounts in the Summa contra gentiles ( 1259-
64), the Compendium theologiae (ca. 1265-67), the Quaestiones dispu-
tatae de anima ( 1265-68), the Quaestio Disputata De Spiritualibus
Creaturis ( 1267-68), the Commentary on the De Anima
of
Aristotle ( 1267-
1268), and the Summa theologiae (1267-1268). However, his first critical
engagement with the doctrine
of
Averroes on the intellect
is
found in his
Scriptum super Sententiis (1252-1257) at book 2,
d.
17,
q.
2,
a.
I, entitled,
I.
This
study is a
product
of
the Aquinas
and
the
Arai>s
Project.
For
information.
see
www
.AquinasAndTheArabs.org.
2.
AVERROES,
Commentarium
Mal!.llllm
in
Aristotelis Oe Anima Lihros, ed.
Crawford.
Hereafter
this work will be
cited
as LCOA with
page
numbers
in brackets
{}.An
English
translation
of
this is
now
available. See T
AYLOR-DRUART
(2009).
This
translation will be
cited in what follows as LCOA,
Taylor,
tr.
Philosophical Psychology in Arabic Thought and the
Aristotelianism of the 13th Century, Luis Xavier
López-Farjeat & Jörg Alejandro Tellkamp, ed.
(Paris: J. Vrin, 2013), 142-183 & 279-296
'li1
I'
1:,]
142
RICHARD
C
TAYLOR
"Whether
there is
one
soul
or
intellect for all human
beings"'·
Posed
in this
fashion, the question
driving
his analysis is seen by
Aquinas
to
bear
upon
the teachings
of
Theophrastus,
Alexander
of
Aphrodisias,
Themistius,
Avicenna,
and
Ibn
Bajjah
(Avempace),
as well as
Averroes
4, since, as
Aquinas
writes,
nearly all
the
philosophers
after
Aristotle
are
in
agreement
that the
agent
intellect
and
the
possible
[intellect]
differ
in
substance
and
that
the
agent
intellect is a
certain
separate
substance
both
last
among
the
separate
intelligences
and
related to the
possible
intellect as that
by
which
we
understand,
as
higher
intelligences
[are related] to
the
souls
of
the
spheres:;_
In forming this view
of
post-Aristotelian philosophy
Aquinas
drew
primarily upon two philosophical sources: (i) the
LonK
Commentwy
by
A verroes for all the teachings
of
the
other
philosophers mentioned above
and for the doctrine
and
arguments
of
Averroes
himself
and
(ii)the
Latin
translation
of
Avicenna's
De Anima for the Persian
philosopher's
own
teachings on the soul 6. In the present article and the translation in the
Appendix, my primarly focus is on the use
of
A verroes by
Aquinas
though
the important role
of
Avicenna
in the
development
of
the thought
of
Aquinas on
epistemology
will also be addressed.
In the first section
below
I
provide
an analysis
of
Aquinas's
accounts
of
his philosophical predecessors and
of
their reasoning for their positions
3. A
provisional
text
of
this
article
of
Aquinas's
Commenrary
on
rile
Sentences
of
Peter
Lom/Jard
was
prepared
by
the
late P.-M.
Gils.
0.
P. My
English
translation
is found in the
Appendix
at the
end
of
this
book. My
thanks
to Dr.
Adriano
Oliva.
0.
P.,
president
of
the
Commissio
Leonina.
for
providing
the
provisional
Latin text
used
here.
My
thanks
also to
Prof. Isabelle
Moulin
for
her
helpful
comments
on
a
draft
of
my
translation.
4.lt
is
curious
that
Aquinas
neglects
to
mention
al-Farabi
in this
context
since
the
latter's
Lerrer on tile
Intellect
orne
illfellnru
was
available
in Latin
translation.
Perhaps
the
reason
for this
was
that this
work
was
not
easily
at
hand
for
Aquinas.
Another
reason
may
be that.
while he
made
extensive
use
of
the
Long
Commentary
on
til<'
/)e
A11111111
of'
Aristotle
b)
Averroes
as will he
shown
below,
he did not fully
understand
the critical
accounts
of
the
teachings
ofal-Farabi
as set forth by
Averroes.
The
Latin
text
ofai-Farabi's
ne
lnrellenu
was
edited
and
discussed
by
Etienne
GILSON ( 1929).
4-149:
sec I 15-126.
For
a
discussion
of
the
importance
of
the
teachings
of
al-Farabi
to the
development
of
the
thought
of
Aquinas.
see
TAYLOR
(2006).
151-168.
For
a
general
account
of
the
thought
of
al-Farahl.
see
DA
VIDSO.'>
( 1992).
44-73:
and
REISMAN
(2005).
52-71
5. A()l'II\AS./112
Snu
..
d.
17.
</-
2.
o.
I. sol.
Sec
Appendix.
Solution.
section
[CJ.
6.
Among
the key
texts
in
Averroes
arc
LCnA
Book
3.
Texts
and
Comments
5. 18-20.
and
36.
For
AVICEI\'IA. the key text IS
Kirci/J
ai-Sifii',
ui-Nall.
Part 5. ed.
F.
Rahman.
202-269:
AVICE'I'IA LATIN\IS. Li/Jer
f>e
Anima
.1eu
Sexru.1
tie Narum/i/Ju.l
1-1/-111,
cd. S. Van Riel.
Li/Jer
/)e
A111ma
seu Snru.1 tie Narum/i/Ju.1 IV-
V.
S.
cd. Van Rict. vol. 2.
69-185.
,
AQUINAS
AND
'THE
ARABS'
143
together with his critical rejection
of
their views asserting in various
ways
that
human
intellect
or
intellective soul is one for all
human
beings.
This
will
make
clear
his
own
impressive
depth
of
understanding
of
his sources
as well as his sophisticated critical insights into
arguments
relevant to the
formation
of
his
own
quite distinct doctrine. I will also indicate important
limitations
of
his
understanding
of
the philosophical teachings
of
his
chief
source, A verroes,
of
which
Aquinas
was unaware.
As
we
shall see,
consideration
of
those
teachings
will go far toward saving A verroes from
definitive refutation by Aquinas. In the
second
section I focus on
Aquinas's
exposition
of
his
own
teaching
on the nature
of
the intellect
or
intellective soul
and
provide
an analysis
of
the
arguments
and presup-
positions underlying his novel
account
of
the multiplicity
of
individual
human
intellects and
of
the multiplication
of
sets
of
intelligible species in
individual intellects. I then
conclude
with a
summary
and
some
remarks
about
Aquinas's
natural
and
supernatural epistemologies.
I.
AQUINAS
ON
THE
UNITY
OF
INTELLECT
IN
"NEARLY
ALL
THE
PHILOSOPHERS
AFTER
ARISTOTLE''
Thomas
[A] 7
begins
his solution to the issue
of
whether
there is
one
intellect
or
one
intellective soul for all
human
beings by stipulating, first,
that he will not
consider
here views that there exists
just
one
intellect for all
reality
or
that the intellect is nothing
but
the divine
essence
and, second,
that his main
concern
will be the unity and diversity
of
the human rational
soul.
While
he treats
of
this issue in
Avicenna,
Alexander,
Theophrastus
and
Themistius,
Ibn
Bajja
(Avempace),
and
Averroes, it is clear that his
primary source is the Long Commentary by A verroes and that his
chief
concern
is the
challenge
posed
by the doctrine
of
intellect
set
forth in that
work.
This
is
evident
[B] in his
account
of
the terminology
of
intellect:
possible intellect, agent intellect and intellect in a positive disposition
(intellectus
in
habitu) 8
which
is
based
on
this
work
by Averroes.
For
his
explanation
that this is a state
consequent
upon the attainment
of
abstracted
knowledge
which
enables
the intellect to operate
per
se 9,
Aquinas
draws
on
Averroes
who
holds the intellect in a positive
disposition
7.
These
bracketed
references
are
to
my
divisions
of
the
text
found
in
the
translation
in
the
Appendix.
8.
This
is
ul-'oql
/Ji-1-molaku/i. In my
translations
of
the
LCnA.
I
render
intellecrus in
lw/Jiru as
"intellect
in a
positive
disposition"
9.AQL'It\AS,/n2Senr.d.l7.q.2.a.l,sol.:section[B].
i
144
RICHARD
C.
TAYLOR
to
refer
to
the human being who
is
the one understanding.
It
is
necessary
to
add
in
the account: insofar as it makes
it
understand everything
in
its own
right and when
it
wishes. For this
is
the definition
of
a positive disposition.
namely, that what has a positive disposition understands
in
virtue
of
it
what
is
proper
to
itself
in
its own right and when
it
wishes, without
it
being the
case that
it
needs something external
in
this
IO
In contrast, for the Latin Avicenna read by Aquinas, the intellect
in
habitu or intellect
in
a positive disposition instead
is
a disposition
of
the
intellect
in
virtue
of
the possession
of
general principles
of
the
understanding
known
per
se such as that a thing cannot he and not he in the
same
respect at the
same
time
11
. A similar affinity for the phraseology
found
in
A verroes
can
also he seen
in
the initial definitions used by
Aquinas for the agent intellect and possible intellect
12
, this latter called
"material intellect" by both A vicenna and Averroes, a term bequeathed to
the tradition by
Alexander
of
Aphrodisias
13
.
The
description
of
Aquinas
coincides broadly with the functions attributed to these intellects by both
these thinkers, though A vicenna and A verroes have strongly contrasting
differences
in
the details, as
Aquinas
will make clear. Here Aquinas
describes the possible intellect as
"what
is
in
potency for receiving all
understood
forms"
14
For
Avicenna the material intellect
is
a
"pure
aptitude" (aptitudo pura)
15
for "universal intelligible intentions altogether
separate from matter"
16
. For Averroes the material intellect
is
said to have
"no
nature according to this except the nature
of
the possibility for
receiving intelligible material forms"
17
and to he defined as "that which
is
I 0. A VERROEs.
LC/M
{
438)
Taylor
tr., 350:
"[
.. ] Referri ad
hominem
intelligentem.
Et
oportct
addere
in
sermone:
secundum
quod
facit
ipsum
intelligere
omne
ex
se
et
quando
volucrit.
Hec
enim
est
diftinitio
habitus,
scilicet
ut
habens
habitum
intelligat
per
ipsum
illud
quod
est
sibi
proprium
ex
se
et
quando
voluerit,
absque
eo
quod
indigeat
in hoc
aliquo
extrinseco"
II.
A
VIC'ENNA
LATI~·HIS,
f)~
An
una V I,
81.78-82:
Arabic,
209.
12.
The
term
"possible
intellect"
is
taken
from ARISTOTLE, Oe
Anima
429a21-24.
13.
See
ALEXANDER
OF
APHRODISIAS, Oe Anima U/Jer Cum Mantissa.
ed.
lvo
Bruns,
81.24.
14. AQtiiNAS,
In
2 Sent. d. 17, q. 2,
a.
I, sol. A
vcrroes
provides
a
precise
definition
oft
he
material
intellect: AVERROES, LCOA,
{387):
Taylor
tr
..
304:
"ldest,
diftinitio
igitur
intellect us
material
is
est
illud
quod
est in
potentia
omnes
intcntiones
formarum
materialium
universalium,
et
non
est in
actu
aliquod
entium
antcquam
intelligat
ipsum".
15.
AVIC'ENNA,
Latin, /)e
Anima
VI,
81.77:
Arabic.
20'1.
16. A VICDit\A, Latin,
/)e
Anima V I.
76.5-6;
Arabic.
206.
17. A
VERROES,
LCf)!l, {
387):
Taylor
tr., 304:
"Non
habet
naturam
secundum
hoc nisi
naturam
possihilitatts
ad
recipiendum
formas
intellectas
matcriales".
Aquinas
writes in
AQt:INAS,/n2
Sent. d. 17. q. 2.
a.
I. sol.:
"Et
dicitur
intellect us
possibilis
qui
est
in
potentia
ad
Jill""""
AQUINAS
AND
'THE ARABS'
145
in potency all the intentions
of
universal material forms and is not any
of
the beings in act he fore it understands any
of
them"
1
8,
functioning as "the
subject
of
the theoretical intelligihles and
of
the agent intellect"
19
.
Regarding
the agent intellect,
Aquinas
writes that this term
"names
what
makes intelligihles in potency to he [intelligihles] in act, as light which
makes colors visible in potency to be visible in act" 20.
The
agent intellect
performs that function for both
Avicenna
and Averroes. However, for
Avicenna it
is
more properly understood as
"the
intellect in act" which
causes the
human
soul to go from potency to act hy giving separate
or
abstract intelligible form to the soul by way
of
emanation
2t.
For
Averroes,
the agent intellect
"makes
that intellect which is in potency to understand
everything in act"
22
and
"makes
everything intelligible in potency to be
intelligible in act after it
was
in
potency"
23, not hy emanation hut hy a
genuine abstraction when an imagined intention "is transferred
in
its being
from one
order
into another" 24
With
the clarification
of
the vocabulary
of
intellect complete,
Aquinas
states directly what motivates the discussion
of
the intellect
in
this his first theological work.
These
two accounts
of
agent intellect and possible intellect differ in
substance and must he rejected according to Aquinas [C]
as
entailing
consequences
deeply contrary to the Catholic faith.
For
while the philoso-
phers hold that the conjoining
of
human beings to the agent intellect yields
ultimate
human
perfection
of
knowing
and thereby ultimate human
happiness, such a view would
mean
that
human
salvation would he brought
about by a separate intelligence
or
angel and not by
God
Himself. Noting
that
some
Catholic teachers seek to correct and in part accept this view hy
recipiendum
omnes
formas
intellectas,
sicut
uisus
est
in
potentia
ad
recipiendum
omnes
col
ores".
18.
See
note
14
fort
he text.
19. A
VERROES,
LCf)A {
499):
Taylor
tr
..
398:
"Nos
autem
cum
posuerimus
intellectum
materialem
esse
eternum
et
intellecta
speculativa
esse
generabilia
et
corruptibilia
eo
modo
quo
diximus,
et
quod
intellect us
materialis
intelligit
utrunque,
scilicet
formas
materiales
et
fonnas
abstractas.
manifestum
est
quod
subiectum
intellectorum
speculativorum
et
intellectus
agent
is
secundum
hunc
modum
est
idem
et
unum.
scilicet
material
is"
20. AQUINAS,/n2 Sent. d.
17.q.
2, a.
I,
sol.:
section
[B].
21.
AVIC'ENNA,
Latin,
De
Anima V 5,
126.28-127.47:
Arabic,
234-35.
22. A
VERROES.
LCD
!I
{
437):
Taylor
tr
..
349:
"[
.. ]
Facit
intellectum
qui
est in
potentia
intelligere
omnia
in
actu
".
23. A
VERROES,
LCf)!l {
438):
Taylor
tr..
350:
"Facit
omnern
rem
intellectam
in
potentia
intellectam
in
actu
postquam
erat
in
potentia".
24. AVERROES. LCf)A {
439):
Taylor
tr., 351:
"[
.. I
Transferri
in
suo
esse
de
ordine
in
ordinem".
On
the
roots
of
this
notion
in
al-Farabi,
see
Taylor
(2006
).
.I
IIi
II
!
146
RICHARD
C.
TAYLOR
identifying the
agent
intellect with
God
25,
since
"by
devotion to
Him
our
soul is blessed, which they
confirm
in virtue
of
what is written at John I,
9:
He
was the true light which illumines all human beings coming into this
world",
Aquinas
here is
content
that their view
has
a certain reason-
ableness, though he
himself
rejects that view 26. In the
present
context,
then, his motivation is clearly
and
expressly theological, though, as we
shall see, his
engagement
with the philosophical tradition will be on philo-
sophical grounds.
Aquinas
proceeds
[D J to his critical analysis
of
the views
of
the
philosophers
on the unity
of
intellect by
considering
those
of
Alexander
of
Aphrodisias, Ibn Bajja
(Avempace),
Avicenna,
Theophrastus
and
Themistius, and finally Averroes, dividing them into three groups.
The
first [E-Gj
is
that
of
Alexander
and Ibn Bajja
(Avempace)
who
regard the
possible intellect as corruptible with the body.
The
second
[Hj is that
of
A vicenna
who
holds the possible intellect to be multiplied
and
distinct in
individual
human
beings, with its subject not the body
or
a bodily
power
but the
essence
of
the rational soul itself, and to
come
into being with the
human body but to persist in existence after the death
of
the body 27.
The
third view [I-M] is that ''the
possible
intellect is
one
for all [human beings],
which
Aquinas
subdivides
into two: [I] the view
of
Themistius
and
Theophrastus
with [J] a refutation by A verroes and [K-M] the view
of
Averroes with [N] a refutation by Aquinas. Aquinas
concludes
the Solutio
with his
own
views
[0-P]
which involve
accepting
principles from
Avicenna
and
Averroes
and incoporating them into his
own
understanding
of
agent intellect and possible intellect as
powers
belonging
individually to
particular
human souls. However, with the exception
of
two
sentences
on
the teaching
ofAvicenna
[H], the sole source for
Aquinas
on these thinkers
appears to be the Long Commemary by A vermes.
25.
This
may
include
William
of
Auvergne
and
Roger
Bacon
among
others.
See
GILSON
(I '126-27). 5-127; in
particular,
67-72.
26.
Note
that
Aquinas
rejects
this v1ew
in
all his
works
with
the
exception
of
a
brief
and
troubling
remark
in his late [)e
1111itate
intel/ectu.1
where
he
mentions
that the
principle
of
intellectual
light is a
separate
substance.
"uel
Deus
secundum
Catholicos.
uel
intelligentia
ultima
secundum
Avicennam"
("either
God
according
to
Catholics
or
the
last
intelligence
according
to
Aviccnna").
See
AQUINAS.
ne
Ullltate intel/euus.
V,
368-70, 314.
On
this
issue.
see LIBERA (2004
).
497-S.
27.
This
is an
accurate
account
of
the
view
of
Aviccnna
available
111
Latin texts.
Sec
the
brief
account
of
Avicenna's
view by WISNOVSKY (2005), 92-136,
spccitically
96-J 05.
Also
see
WISNOVSKY (2003),
Ch.
6
"Avicenna
on
Perfection
and
Soul.
The
Issue
of
Separability",
I 13-141.
Also
sec
DA
VID>ON
( 1992).
~
AQUINAS AND 'THE ARABS'
147
Alexander
of
Aphrodisias
and
Ibn
Bajjah
Following
closely the Long CommentaJy by Averroes, Aquinas
argues
[E] that
Alexander
28 held
"that
the possible intellect is nothing
other
than a
disposition
29
which
is in
human
nature for receiving the impressions
of
the
agent intellect
and
that this is a bodily
power
consequent
upon the
human
constitution"
30. In the
work
of
Averroes
he found the following
quotation
from the Arabic version
of
the De intellectu
of
Alexander.
Since, therefore, from this body,
when
it is mixed in a certain mixture,
something
will be
generated
from the
whole
mixture such that it is fit for
being
an
instrument
of
that intellect
which
is in this
mixed
thing, since it
exists
in all the body, and that
instrument
is also a body, then it will be
called the intellect in potency. It is a
power
made
from a mixture
which
occurred
in
bodies, [a power]
disposed
to receive
the
intellect
which
is in
act
3t.
28.
The
[)e imel/ectu
of
Alexander
was
available
in
Latin
translation
from
Arabic,
but
Aquinas
makes
no
use
of
it
here
and
instead
relies
completely
on
Averroes.
R. A.
Gauthier
in
his
introduction
to
the
Leonine
edition
of
Aquinas's
Commentary on the
De
Anima
finds
that
Aquinas
never
directly
read
this
treatise
by
Alexander.
See
AQUINAS, Sententia de anima,
Opera omnia
XLV,
I,
ed.
R.
A.
Gauthier,
230-31.
Averroes
himself
had
in
Arabic
translation
both
Alexander's
the
paraphrasing
De Anima
and
his
De
intellectu.
See
AVERROES, LCDA,
Taylor,
tr.,
introduction,
lxxxi-lxxxii;
and
DAVIDSON ( 1992). 259-60.
The
Latin
translation
of
the
ne
intel/ectu is
edited
by
THERY ( 1926), 3-120;
see
74-82.
29.preparationem.
The
corresponding
Greek
is epitedeiotes.
See
ALEXANDER
OF
APIIRODISIAS,
De
Anima Liher Cum Mantissa,
ed.
lvo
Bruns,
[Commentaria
in
Aristotelem
Graeca,
Suppl.
It,
pt.
1],
84.24-85.5.
30. A
VERROES.
LCDA ( 444};
Taylor.
tr., 355:
"Qui
dam
enim
dicunt
intellectum
possibilem
nichil
aliud
esse
quam
preparationem
que
est
in
natura
humana
ad
recipiendam
impressionem
intellectus
agentis,
et
hanc
esse
uirtutcm
corporalem
consequentem
complexionem
humanam".
In
lines
134-137
we
lind,
"Potest
enim
intelligi
secundum
Alexandrum
quod
intendebat
per
intellectum
in
potentia
preparationem
existentem
in
complexione
humana,
scilicet
quod
potentia
et
preparatio
que
est
in
homine
ad
recipiendum
intellectum
in
respectu
uniuscuiusque
individui
est
prior
tempore
intellectu
agenti".
In
the
text
that
immediately
follows
Averroes
explains
that
this
intelligible
comes
about
when
the
immortal
Agent
Intellect
is
united
to
us
as
"form
for
us",jimua
nobis,
according
to
Alexander.
31. A
VERROES,
LC
DA
( 394};
Taylor
tr., 310:
"Cum
igit
ur
ex
hoc
corpore,
quando
fuerit
mixtum
aliqua
mixtione,
generabitur
aliquid
ex
universo
mixti
ita
quod
sit
aptum
ut
sit
instrumentum
istius
intellectus
qui
est
in
hoc
mixto,
cum
cxistit
in
omni
corpore.
et
istud
instrumentum
est
etiam
corpus,
tunc
dicetur
esse
intellectus
in
potentia;
et
est
virtus
facta
a
mixtione
que
cecidit
in
corporibus,
preparata
ad
recipiendum
intellectum
qui
est
in
actu".
For
the
Greek,
see
ALEXANDER
OF
APitRODIStAS, De Anima
Liha
Cum Mantissa. ed.
lvo
Bruns.
112.11-16.
On
the
unsatisfactory
status
of
the
editions
of
the
Arabic
of
the
De lntellectu,
see
DAVIDSON
( 1992), 7 n.
2.
It,
I
148
RICHARD
C.
TAYLOR
For his criticism
of
Alexander
that the possible intellect is intended by
Aristotle to be itself receptive
of
intelligible species and that Aristotle
refutes the notion that intelligible forms may be received into a body
or
a
power
in
a body, Aquinas relies wholly on
Averroes's
refutation
of
Alexander
in
the Long Commentary32. Aquinas saw
in
Averroes
himself
a
great disdain for the materialist view
of
Alexander
where A verroes writes,
A more unthinkable aspect
of
the opinion
of
Alexander
is that he said that
the first dispositions for the intelligibles and for the
other
later actualities
of
the soul are things produced from the mixture, not
powers
produced
by an
external
mover
as is well
known
of
the opinion
of
Aristotle and all the
Peripatetics. For that opinion regarding the
apprehensive
powers
of
the
soul,
if
it is as we have understood it, is false.
For
from the
substance
and the
nature
of
the
elements
there
cannot
come
to be an
apprehensive
discerning
power.
For
if
it were possible that there
come
to be such
powers
from their
nature and without an external mover, then it
would
be
possible for the final
actuality,
which
is the intelligibles, to be
something
produced
from the
substance
of
their
elements,
as
color
and taste
come
to be.
This
opinion is
similar
to the opinion
of
those
who
deny
agent
causes
and those
who
allow
only material causes: these are those
who
speak
of
chance.
Alexander
has
greater
nobility than to believe this, but the
questions
which
were
posed to
him regarding the material intellect forced him to this [position]
JJ_
32. A
VERROES.
LCf)A
{ 395-6}: Taylor. tr
..
312:
"Sed
hoc
quod
dixit Alexander nichil
est. Hoc
enim
vere
dicitur
de omni preparatione, scilicet quod neque est
corpus
neque forma
hec in corpore. Quare igitur appropriavit Aristotcles hoc preparationi
que
est in intellectu inter
alias preparationes,
si
non intendebat demonstrare nobis substantiam preparati sed
substantiam preparationis'i Sed impossibile est dicere quod preparatio est substantia,
cum
hoc
quod dicimus
quod
subiectum istius preparationis neque est
corpus
neque virtus in corpore.
Et
est illud
quod
conclusit demonstratio Aristotelis alia intcntio ab
ea
secundum
quam
dicitur
quod preparatio neque est
corpus
neque virtus
in
corpore.
Et
hoc manifestum est ex
demonstratione Aristotelis. Propositio
enim
dicens
quod
omne
recipiens aliquid necesse est
ut
in
eo
non existat in actu aliquid ex natura recepti manifesta est ex
eo
quod
substantia preparati
et natura eius querit habere hoc predicatum secundum quod est preparatum. Preparatio
enim
non est recipiens. sed
esse
preparationis a recipiente est sicut accidentis proprii. Et ideo.
cum
fuerit receptio, non erit preparatio, et remanebit recipiens.
Et
hoc manifestum est et
intellcctum
ahomnihus
expositoribus ex demonstratione Aristotelis".
33.
AVERROES,
LCDA {
397-8
}:
Taylor, tr., 314: "Et magis inopinabile de opinione
Alexandri est hoc
quod
dixit
quod
prime preparationes ad intellecta et ad alias postremas
perfectiones de anima sunt res facte a complexione, non virtutes facte a mot ore extrinseco
ut
est famosum ex
opinione
Aristotelis et
omnium
Peripateticorum. lsta
enim
opimo in
virtutihus anime comprehensivis.
si
est secundum quod nos intelleximus. est falsa. A
substantia
enim elementorum
eta
natura
eorum
non potest fieri virtus distinguens compre-
hensiva: quoniam,
si
esset possibile
ut
a natura
eorum
et sine extrinseco mot ore tierent tales
virtutes. tunc esset possibile
ut
postrema pcrfectio. que est intellect
a.
esset aliquod fact urn a
~·t:
AQUINAS
AI\:D
'THE
ARABS'
149
Here A verroes (i) attacks
Alexander's
notion
of
the receptive material
intellect as
"an
apprehensive discerning
power"
which arises from a
mixture
of
physical elements. A verroes later goes on to rail at length
(ii) against what he characterizes as
Alexander's
impossible notion that
somehow
the disposition for receptivity
called
the material intellect might
be
a disposition
somehow
distinct from a subject such as a body or a
power
of
a body, saying
of
Alexander's
account,
"I
am
ashamed
of
this account
and
of
this fantastic
exposition"
34. Futhermore, according to Averroes,
(iii) given that a disposition must
be
in a subject,
one
must reject "the
impossible results [reached] by Alexander, namely, that the subject
receiving the intelligible forms
is
a body
made
from the elements
or
a
power
in a
body"
35_
It
is
precisely on these three points that Aquinas refutes
the view
of
Alexander: (i)
"no
power
caused by the
commixture
of
elements is able to
know";
(ii)
"a
disposition
is
not [itself] receptive but
rather something which has been disposed [is receptive];" and (iii)
"what
is
disposed by this disposition is a body
or
a
power
in a body, and in such a
way that what receives intelligible forms would be a body
or
a
power
in a
substantia
eorum
elementorum
ut
color
et
sapor
fiunt.
Et
ista opinio
est
similis opinioni
negantium causas agentes et non
concedentium
nisi causas materiales: et sunt illi qui dicunt
casum.
Sed
Alexander est maioris nobilitatis
quam
ut
credat hoc; sed questiones
que
opponebanturei
in intellectu materiali coegerunt ipsum ad hoc".
34.
AVER
ROES,
LCDA { 430-431 } : Taylor, tr., 344: "Dicere autem quod intellect us
material
is
est simi lis preparationi
que
est in tabula, non tabule secundum
quod
est preparata,
ut exponit
Alexander
hunc
sermonem,
falsum est. Preparatio
enim
est privatio aliqua,
et
null am habet naturam propriam nisi propter naturam subiecti. et propter hoc fuit possibile ut
preparationes diversentur in unoquoque ente. 0 Alexander. reputas Aristotelem intendere
demonstrare nobis naturam preparationis tantum, non naturam preparati ( et non est natura
istius preparation
is
propriaei,
si
fuerit possibile sine cognitione nature preparati), sed naturam
preparationis simpliciter. in
quocunque
sit? Ego autem verecundor ex hoc sermone et ex hac
mirabili expositione. Si
enim
Aristoteles intendebat demonstrare naturam preparationis
que
est in intellectu per
omnes
sermones
predictos in intellectu materiali, necesse est aut
ut
intendat demonstrare per eos naturam preparationis simpliciter, aut naturam preparationis
proprie. Naturam autem preparationis proprie intellectui impossibile est demonstrari sine
natura subiecti,
cum
preparatio propria unicuique subiecto currit cursu perfectionis
et
forme
ex eo: sed oportet necessaria per cognitionem nature preparationis scire naturam preparati.
Et
si
intendebat per illos
sermones
demonstrare
naturam preparationis simpliciter, tunc illud non
est proprium intellectui. et
omne
hoc est perturbatio.
Omnis
enim
preparatio,
in
eo
quod est
preparatio, vere dicitur nichil
esse
in actu ex eis
que
recipit.
ct
quod est non passibile. et vere
dicituresse
non corpus neque virtus in corpore".
35. Averroes, LCJ)A { 397}:
Taylor
tr
..
313: "[
...
Jimpossihilia
contingentia Alexandro.
scilicet quod subiectum recipiens form as intellectas est corpus factum ah elementis, aut virtus
in
corpore[
...
]".
1 / 36 100%

Aquinas, Avicenna, Averroes on the Intellect 2013

Telechargé par C. Bordeleau
La catégorie de ce document est-elle correcte?
Merci pour votre participation!

Faire une suggestion

Avez-vous trouvé des erreurs dans linterface ou les textes ? Ou savez-vous comment améliorer linterface utilisateur de StudyLib ? Nhésitez pas à envoyer vos suggestions. Cest très important pour nous !